critiqueofliberalism
上传者:曹计昌|上传时间:2015-05-09|密次下载
critiqueofliberalism
The Conservative Critique of Liberalism
John Skorupski
University of St Andrews
1
1. Philosophical Liberalism and Liberal Order
There is a philosophical critique of liberalism that hangs together, can properly be said to be conservative, has a considerable tradition behind it, and is interesting and important. But it takes some effort, historical and philosophical, to locate it.
A first task is to dispel some terminological haze. ‘Liberalism’ has come to mean many, often incompatible, things. American critics of ‘liberalism’ and French critics of ‘(neo-)liberalism’, for example, have quite different things in mind. Critics of ‘liberalism’ in one sense may themselves be ‘liberals’ in another. Likewise with the word ‘conservatism’. It can denote (1) a tough-minded version of liberalism that places emphasis on free exchange, a small but strong state, private initiative and individual responsibility. This, or something in this area, is what people mean by ‘neo-liberalism’. Then (2) there is a practical, down-to-earth attitude which we can call practical conservatism. Practical conservatives see virtue in keeping the show on the road – conserving and when necessary refreshing institutions and habits that work, whatever they are. They know that sometimes ‘If we want things to stay as they are, things will have to change.’1 But they may well take pride in having no philosophical view, unless it be an anti-abstract one. Importantly, they make no universal claims; what works is what works here. Finally (3) there is conservatism in the sense of an attitude that sees continuity, community, tradition and hierarchy as organic elements of a good society, and gives ethical grounds for doing so. In this chapter we shall be interested mainly in (3), but also in (2) in so far as it incorporates an anti-
universalistic attitude.
Distinguished from these two conservative views is another outlook, viscerally hostile to liberalism, but which it is misleading to think of as either ‘conservative’, or ‘left’ – it is too out of sorts with modernity, or the ‘Enlightenment’, to be either. I shall come back to it in section 5.
What then is liberalism? We should distinguish two levels. At an intellectual level liberalism is a set of ideas that hang together as a moral and political philosophy; at the political level it is a political ethos that provides a framework for policy. At both levels it is a broad church with left and right wings. Our concern is with
conservative criticisms from outside the broad church, not the debates of left and right within it; and our focus will be on the underlying philosophical issues, that is, on philosophical liberalism.
I shall refer to the policy-framing level of liberalism as the liberal order. It comprises (i) equal liberty for all citizens, of which an essential element is the right to act as one chooses subject to a law that protects the equal rights of others; (ii) a distinctive and special protection of liberty of thought and discussion, and (iii) the entrenchment of these principles, either in an effective legal framework that codifies them in basic laws or constitutional safeguards guaranteeing equality of every citizen under law, or (perhaps) in a common law tradition that effectively does the same. 1 Tancredi’s remark to the Prince, in The Leopard (Lampedusa, 1960, p. 27). More sententiously: “A state without the means of some change is without the means of its conservation” Burke, 1967 (1790), p. 19
2
Behind the liberal order have stood ideas that flow from a long philosophical tradition. They can be traced back to natural law theorists, and philosophers such as Locke or Montesquieu. However, while important elements of liberalism were present in early modern Europe they came together in the specific unified form, which I shall describe as philosophical liberalism,2 only after the French Revolution. One
important feature of this new outlook is that liberals came to recognize dangers on the left as well as on the right, and to seek principled grounds on which to distinguish themselves from both. Another is that they took on board philosophical and romantic critiques of the Enlightenment. By the same token, it was also in the nineteenth century that significant criticisms of philosophical liberalism emerged on the left as well as on the right.
With this context in mind we can set out the philosophical liberalism that
conservatives reject. Think of it as comprising three principal tenets, intertwined and all contested by one or another kind of philosophical conservative:
? Individualism in ethics. This is the view that all value and right reduces to value of or for individuals, or to the rights of individuals.
? A doctrine of equal respect for all human beings based on the belief that all are equally capable of self-governance.
? A doctrine of liberty of thought and discussion based on belief in the unrestricted autonomy of reason – that is, the rational capacities of individual people – as the sole and sufficient canon of objective truth.
It is easy to pay lip service to these theses; taken seriously they are strong doctrine. Their shape and strength will become clearer as we consider criticisms. However, before coming to them let me note some other limits that I am placing on the liberalism that critics target.
First, I have not included the right to democratic participation as a defining part of liberal political order. We may think that democratic rights of participation in collective self-government follow from the basic philosophical outlook of liberalism that I have just described; alternatively, that if they do not then they should simply be added to the liberal order on good grounds of their own. Either way we tend to think of ‘liberal democracy’ as a package deal. However the idea that liberalism and
democracy are necessarily linked is quite a recent development. It is not obvious that liberalism entails democracy or indeed that democracy entails liberalism.3 Many liberals have worried that democracy might turn out to be incompatible with liberal order, and if it is, they have been ready to prefer liberalism to unrestricted democracy. The view that democracy could be inimical to liberty was influential at least to the end of World War II, deriving, earlier, from the Federalist Papers, then Tocqueville’s account of democracy in America and, later and more dramatically, from the experience of political cataclysm in early twentieth-century Europe.
To highlight the conceptual distinction between democracy and liberal order, imagine a meritocracy in which the ruling class is selected on a self-perpetuating basis 2 Or ‘classical’ liberalism – where by the word ‘classical’ I refer to the philosophical liberalism that emerged at this time, not to an economic theory of free markets. (See, for example, the distinction Mill makes, in On Liberty, ch 5, para. 4, between the liberty principle which he there argues for, and the doctrine of free trade which, as he says, rests on different grounds; compare his nuanced discussion of laisser-faire in the Principles of Political Economy, Bk V, ch. 11.) 3 In the 1920s Carl Schmitt’s aim was to “rescue democracy from its overlay of liberal elements” (quoted in Holmes 1993, p. 49).
3 by open examination, with no discrimination by class, gender, race etc. It nonetheless runs a liberal state. It honours the tenet of equal liberty by placing no restriction on entry to the examination and promoting strictly according to talent, and it entrenches negative liberty and liberty of thought and discussion. Hegel’s conception of the role of the civil servant estate within his ideal constitution is not so far from this. He was highly critical of the philosophical liberal’s first tenet – liberal individualism – and of democracy; but he was nonetheless a proponent of liberal order, though a
conservative one. An interestingly similar standpoint seems to be evolving in some intellectual circles in China.4 So conservatives may approve liberal order without approving either philosophical liberalism or democracy; philosophical liberals may reject democracy in whole or part; and democrats may reject liberalism.
True, one can argue that the liberal’s philosophical thesis of equal respect
creates at least a prima facie case for unconditional equal rights of political
participation. And at the empirical level one can argue – contrary to evidence brought up by those who disagree – that once the right social conditions have been reached, democracy is not only a stable long-term setting for liberal order but also a reliable one. I myself find both these arguments quite plausible. Here however we are
focusing on the conservative critique of philosophical liberalism itself, and this will not require us to examine its relationship to democracy, except at the very end.5
Turning to a second point: I take philosophical liberalism to hold that the three normative theses outlined above are quite simply correct, hence in principle
universally applicable – relevant to all societies at least in respect of setting goals for social development. Importantly, this epistemological claim is quite compatible with empirical recognition that the historical and social conditions for liberal order must be right. Still the historicism of a liberal like Mill in this regard, however striking, is very different to the standpoint of a practical conservative, who endorses and works to maintain the liberal political order only as ‘what works here.’ For a philosophical liberal, liberal order is universally the ideally best order; it’s just that a process of development must take place for a civil society that can maintain it successfully to emerge. In contrast, a practical conservative may well simply regard the three liberal theses as what we have come to accept, our historically-arrived-at consensus, the tenets that have come to form the cementing allegiances of our society. This anti-universalistic stance will reject or at least eschew the third thesis in its unrestricted liberal version. It is sceptical or agnostic about the claims of natural reason as a canon of truth. In so far as it defends liberal order it will endorse freedom of thought, but not the epistemological underpinnings a philosophical liberal provides for it. Practical conservatism can defend established and continuous liberal traditions; it just does not make any universal claims for them. This is likely to make a difference at the level of policy: a practical conservative might well be against liberal intervention, for example, in cases where even a historically minded liberal favours it.
We could make objectivism about the truth of the three tenets explicit as a fourth tenet of philosophical liberalism; however as just noted it is implicit in the
third. Note also that on this account of philosophical liberalism the rather popular idea that liberalism is based on rejection of the objectivity of values is misguided. A better picture is that non-objectivist forms of liberalism are a strategic retreat from classical 4 See Daniel Bell and Li Chenyang (eds), 2013. A number of papers in this volume make the case for varying degrees of liberal meritocracy. 5 I consider what arguments for and against democracy can be made from a liberal standpoint in Skorupski 2013.
4 liberalism. Many critics from both right and left have attacked the objectivity of liberal values in sceptical, subjectivist or voluntarist terms, and many liberals,
bending to the strength of these epistemological gales, have tried to adapt by finding ways of defending their liberal convictions without committing themselves to their objectivity. We shall come back to this.
Finally, something should be said at this point about the influential ‘political liberalism’ of John Rawls. Seen from the standpoint of the classical liberal tradition Rawls’ liberalism is something of an outlier. In part this is a matter of its content, focused as it is on a strongly egalitarian theory of justice. Rawls fits into the liberal broad church by the priority he gives to liberty in his two principles of justice;6 however in so far as his influence has contributed to the impression that a particular theory of justice is a constituent of liberal order as such, that impression should be corrected. Beyond the debateable minima already implied by the entrenchment of negative liberty, no further, more committal, theory of justice is constitutive of liberal order: indeed this is clearer than the analogous claim that democracy is not constitutive of liberal order.
It is also interesting that in so far as Rawls defends his account of justice on the grounds that it makes explicit the overlapping consensus to be found in Western societies, he adopts the methodology of practical conservatives.7 Practically
conservative, too, is his claim that the very question of whether philosophical (in Rawls’ terms “comprehensive”) liberalism is objectively true should be set aside, i.e. not appealed to in the derivation of ‘political liberalism’. Both these moves distance him from the philosophical liberal.
Two further elements of Rawls’ political liberalism are likely to trouble a
philosophical liberal: the doctrine that the state should not support any comprehensive conception of the good, and, even more, the doctrine of ‘public reason,’ according to which citizens and their representatives, when engaged in political deliberation and decision (including voting), should not appeal to ethical ideas with which other citizens cannot reasonably be expected to agree. Both these stances seem
unnecessarily limiting from a classical-liberal standpoint, and in the second case, potentially illiberal. At any rate they are not constitutive of liberalism as discussed here, and their plausibility is beyond our remit, since our assessment of the conservative critique of liberalism concerns the powerful criticisms it makes of philosophical liberalism, which Rawls’s political liberalism explicitly eschews.
2. The critique of philosophical liberalism (i) individualism
So let us turn to liberal individualism. This is the doctrine that attracts the greatest and most widely-shared hostility, on the left as well as the right – in both cases on behalf of an alternative conception which has come to be labelled ‘communitarian’. In its conservative version it is more precisely described as the rejection of liberals’ ethical individualism in favour of an ethics of conservative holism.
To get to the core of this debate we must eliminate some red herrings. The first of these identifies ethical individualism with egoism and perhaps an egoistically based contractarianism about the state, or about morality. Well, holding this kind of 6 Rawls, 1971, §§39, 82. 7 However some question how much justificatory weight he places on that defence. See Mulhall and Swift, 2003, pp 478 – 81,
5 view does not disqualify you as a liberal, but as a matter of fact no notable
philosopher of liberalism has held it. Hobbes, who did hold this view of the state, is sometimes described as a liberal, but it is unclear why. Locke, in contrast, can surely be described as at least a liberal ancestor, or proto-liberal; however his version of the social contract does not rest on egoistic foundations but on a substantial theory of natural rights. True, some liberal philosophers , such as T. H Green, have founded their liberalism on a kind of ethical egoism, in the formal sense of the word ‘egoism’, but their conception of the true interests of the self is very far from the picture of selfish self-interest – and their metaphysics has been hostile to contractarianism. In fact contractarianism was treated on all sides with a good deal of hostility in liberalism’s nineteenth-century heyday.
Another red herring is the idea that liberalism favours ‘negative’ as against ‘positive’ liberty. Two points here. In the first place, though negative liberty is unquestionably crucial to liberal order, the negative liberty that a liberal order
institutes is not a liberty to do as one likes, without any external constraint. To refer again to Locke:
Freedom is not, as we are told, A Liberty for every Man to do what he lists … But a Liberty to dispose, and order, as he lists, his Person, Actions,
Possessions, and his whole Property, within the Allowance of those Laws under which he is; and therein not to be subject to the arbitrary Will of
another, but freely follow his own.8
This Lockean, as against Hobbesian, conception of negative liberty is the very essence of liberal law.
But second, it is a mistake is to think that liberal individualism is necessarily concerned with negative rather than positive liberty. Classically, it is concerned with both. In Kant’s original formulation of this contrast9 ‘positive liberty’ refers to
autonomy – where by autonomy Kant means acting from recognition of how reason requires one to act. Some subsequent liberal philosophers, starting with Schiller and going on through Mill, wanted to enrich or supplement Kantian autonomy in their ideal of a fully developed individual, but they didn’t want to give it up. Autonomy in Kant’s sense is central to the classical liberal ideal of the person. If a conflict emerges within liberalism between negative and positive liberty, the former understood as a property of liberal order, the latter as an ideal of the person, it centres on the idea that negative liberty may legitimately be constrained by law in order to foster the
development of the capacity for autonomy – as argued against Mill by T. H. Green. We arrive at the real issue when we turn to the characteristic holist claim that individuals abstracted from community are mere abstractions. This claim can be ‘metaphysical’10 but its core is normative and psychological. It is at this point that conservative criticism of liberal individualism demands to be taken seriously.
Human beings are social animals. They gain their actuality and satisfaction from social identities which confer obligation, standing and fullness of life.
Communal obligations arise from the collectivities to which a human being belongs – family, church, corporation, ‘platoon’ – certainly nation and state. Crucially, they are inherently and essentially agent-relative – you have obligations to your family, or 8 Locke, Second Treatise of Government, §57. 9 Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals, IV 446-7. 10 As it was for both idealist and positivist critics of liberal individualism. See Skorupski 2012.
下载文档
热门试卷
- 2016年四川省内江市中考化学试卷
- 广西钦州市高新区2017届高三11月月考政治试卷
- 浙江省湖州市2016-2017学年高一上学期期中考试政治试卷
- 浙江省湖州市2016-2017学年高二上学期期中考试政治试卷
- 辽宁省铁岭市协作体2017届高三上学期第三次联考政治试卷
- 广西钦州市钦州港区2016-2017学年高二11月月考政治试卷
- 广西钦州市钦州港区2017届高三11月月考政治试卷
- 广西钦州市钦州港区2016-2017学年高一11月月考政治试卷
- 广西钦州市高新区2016-2017学年高二11月月考政治试卷
- 广西钦州市高新区2016-2017学年高一11月月考政治试卷
- 山东省滨州市三校2017届第一学期阶段测试初三英语试题
- 四川省成都七中2017届高三一诊模拟考试文科综合试卷
- 2017届普通高等学校招生全国统一考试模拟试题(附答案)
- 重庆市永川中学高2017级上期12月月考语文试题
- 江西宜春三中2017届高三第一学期第二次月考文科综合试题
- 内蒙古赤峰二中2017届高三上学期第三次月考英语试题
- 2017年六年级(上)数学期末考试卷
- 2017人教版小学英语三年级上期末笔试题
- 江苏省常州西藏民族中学2016-2017学年九年级思想品德第一学期第二次阶段测试试卷
- 重庆市九龙坡区七校2016-2017学年上期八年级素质测查(二)语文学科试题卷
- 江苏省无锡市钱桥中学2016年12月八年级语文阶段性测试卷
- 江苏省无锡市钱桥中学2016-2017学年七年级英语12月阶段检测试卷
- 山东省邹城市第八中学2016-2017学年八年级12月物理第4章试题(无答案)
- 【人教版】河北省2015-2016学年度九年级上期末语文试题卷(附答案)
- 四川省简阳市阳安中学2016年12月高二月考英语试卷
- 四川省成都龙泉中学高三上学期2016年12月月考试题文科综合能力测试
- 安徽省滁州中学2016—2017学年度第一学期12月月考高三英语试卷
- 山东省武城县第二中学2016.12高一年级上学期第二次月考历史试题(必修一第四、五单元)
- 福建省四地六校联考2016-2017学年上学期第三次月考高三化学试卷
- 甘肃省武威第二十三中学2016—2017学年度八年级第一学期12月月考生物试卷
网友关注
- 古代神话故事之年的传说和由来
- 下跌休息区的卖点警示标志
- 如何正确决定卖点?股市卖点要怎么决定?
- 神话传说中“龙生九子 凤育九雏”它们各是谁?
- 传说中上古神话史上的十大魔神
- 夏朝的建立相当于西方的亚特兰蒂斯
- 2016年清明节、劳动节放假时间安排
- 短线投资如何能做到卖在最高点
- 元宵节诗词大全
- 2016年中秋节、国庆节放假时间安排
- 年兽究竟是什么兽
- 雅思写作中的“复杂句”是怎么回事?
- 2016年元宵节灯谜大全及答案(字谜)
- 混世四猴都有哪几只
- 2016年猴年元宵节灯谜大全及答案
- 主力出货手法之金钩钓饵式出货法
- 2016年端午节放假时间安排
- 英雄联盟S6上单一霸深海泰坦诺提勒斯
- 股市出货技巧有没有窍门?
- 盘点希腊诸神十大栖居地
- 中国古代传说的幻兽和魔神
- 国务院关于2016年节假日放假安排的通知
- 2016年元宵节灯谜集锦
- 中国神话中的龙一般分哪几种
- 2016年元宵节灯谜大全及答案(动物)
- 我国古代帝王身上的“龙袍”是怎么演变的?
- 英雄联盟S6野兽之灵乌迪尓野区崛起
- 2016年元宵节祝福语短信大全
- 证券市场中典型风险都有哪些?
- 揭秘大唐史:传奇燕王罗艺
网友关注视频
- 苏科版数学八年级下册9.2《中心对称和中心对称图形》
- 第4章 幂函数、指数函数和对数函数(下)_六 指数方程和对数方程_4.7 简单的指数方程_第一课时(沪教版高一下册)_T1566237
- 冀教版小学数学二年级下册第二周第2课时《我们的测量》宝丰街小学庞志荣
- 30.3 由不共线三点的坐标确定二次函数_第一课时(市一等奖)(冀教版九年级下册)_T144342
- 冀教版英语四年级下册第二课
- 苏科版八年级数学下册7.2《统计图的选用》
- 【部编】人教版语文七年级下册《逢入京使》优质课教学视频+PPT课件+教案,安徽省
- 【部编】人教版语文七年级下册《老山界》优质课教学视频+PPT课件+教案,安徽省
- 人教版二年级下册数学
- 苏科版数学 八年级下册 第八章第二节 可能性的大小
- 苏教版二年级下册数学《认识东、南、西、北》
- 《空中课堂》二年级下册 数学第一单元第1课时
- 【部编】人教版语文七年级下册《老山界》优质课教学视频+PPT课件+教案,安徽省
- 七年级英语下册 上海牛津版 Unit5
- 8.练习八_第一课时(特等奖)(苏教版三年级上册)_T142692
- 冀教版英语五年级下册第二课课程解读
- 沪教版八年级下册数学练习册21.3(2)分式方程P15
- 小学英语单词
- 《小学数学二年级下册》第二单元测试题讲解
- 冀教版小学英语五年级下册lesson2教学视频(2)
- 【部编】人教版语文七年级下册《老山界》优质课教学视频+PPT课件+教案,安徽省
- 第五单元 民族艺术的瑰宝_16. 形形色色的民族乐器_第一课时(岭南版六年级上册)_T3751175
- 3月2日小学二年级数学下册(数一数)
- 冀教版英语三年级下册第二课
- 外研版英语七年级下册module3 unit2第二课时
- 【部编】人教版语文七年级下册《过松源晨炊漆公店(其五)》优质课教学视频+PPT课件+教案,辽宁省
- 青岛版教材五年级下册第四单元(走进军营——方向与位置)用数对确定位置(一等奖)
- 沪教版八年级下册数学练习册21.3(3)分式方程P17
- 【获奖】科粤版初三九年级化学下册第七章7.3浓稀的表示
- 【部编】人教版语文七年级下册《泊秦淮》优质课教学视频+PPT课件+教案,天津市
精品推荐
- 2016-2017学年高一语文人教版必修一+模块学业水平检测试题(含答案)
- 广西钦州市高新区2017届高三11月月考政治试卷
- 浙江省湖州市2016-2017学年高一上学期期中考试政治试卷
- 浙江省湖州市2016-2017学年高二上学期期中考试政治试卷
- 辽宁省铁岭市协作体2017届高三上学期第三次联考政治试卷
- 广西钦州市钦州港区2016-2017学年高二11月月考政治试卷
- 广西钦州市钦州港区2017届高三11月月考政治试卷
- 广西钦州市钦州港区2016-2017学年高一11月月考政治试卷
- 广西钦州市高新区2016-2017学年高二11月月考政治试卷
- 广西钦州市高新区2016-2017学年高一11月月考政治试卷
分类导航
- 互联网
- 电脑基础知识
- 计算机软件及应用
- 计算机硬件及网络
- 计算机应用/办公自动化
- .NET
- 数据结构与算法
- Java
- SEO
- C/C++资料
- linux/Unix相关
- 手机开发
- UML理论/建模
- 并行计算/云计算
- 嵌入式开发
- windows相关
- 软件工程
- 管理信息系统
- 开发文档
- 图形图像
- 网络与通信
- 网络信息安全
- 电子支付
- Labview
- matlab
- 网络资源
- Python
- Delphi/Perl
- 评测
- Flash/Flex
- CSS/Script
- 计算机原理
- PHP资料
- 数据挖掘与模式识别
- Web服务
- 数据库
- Visual Basic
- 电子商务
- 服务器
- 搜索引擎优化
- 存储
- 架构
- 行业软件
- 人工智能
- 计算机辅助设计
- 多媒体
- 软件测试
- 计算机硬件与维护
- 网站策划/UE
- 网页设计/UI
- 网吧管理